WWW.ABSTRACT.XLIBX.INFO
FREE ELECTRONIC LIBRARY - Abstract, dissertation, book
 
<< HOME
CONTACTS



Pages:   || 2 |

«ANCIENT ORIGINS OF A MODERN ANTHROPIC COSMOLOGICAL ARGUMENT MILAN M. CIRKOVIC∗ ´ ´ Astronomical Observatory Belgrade, Volgina 7, 11000 Belgrade, ...»

-- [ Page 1 ] --

Astronomical and Astrophysical Transactions

Vol. 22, No. 6, December 2003, pp. 879–886

ANCIENT ORIGINS OF A MODERN ANTHROPIC

COSMOLOGICAL ARGUMENT

MILAN M. CIRKOVIC∗

´ ´

Astronomical Observatory Belgrade, Volgina 7, 11000 Belgrade, Yugoslavia

(Received 18 November 2002)

Ancient origins of a modern anthropic argument against cosmologies involving infinite series of past events are considered. It is shown that this argument – which in modern times has been put forward by distinguished cosmologists such as Paul C. W. Davies and Frank J. Tipler – originates in pre-Socratic times and is implicitly present in the cyclical cosmology of Empedocles. There are traces of the same line of reasoning throughout the ancient history of ideas, and the case of a provocative statement of Thucydides is briefly analysed. Moreover, the anthropic argument has been fully formulated in the epic of Lucretius, confirming it as the summit of ancient cosmology. This not only is of historical significance but also presents an important topic for the philosophy of cosmology provided that some of the contemporary inflationary models, particularly Linde’s chaotic inflation, turn out to be correct.

Keywords: Anthropic argument; Cosmology; Ancient origins

1 INTRODUCTION: DAVIES–TIPLER ARGUMENT

The simplest division of all cosmologies is into two broad classes: those postulating the eternal Universe and those which postulate some origin of the Universe, or at least the part of it that cosmologists are currently inhabiting. Eternal universes (and here by eternal I mean either those with no temporal beginning or end or those with no beginning only) are the only universes that could pretend to adopt some sort of stationarity, a condition which is of singular importance in many branches of physics (among other issues because the law of energy conservation is closely connected with a translational symmetry of time), and which is certainly seen as greatly simplifying the solution of specific problems everywhere. For a long period of time, after the religious dogma about Creation in 4004 BC (or any other specific date) was abandoned, the Universe has been considered eternal, although great minds, such as Newton’s, began to perceive some of the difficulties associated with such a proposition (see for example North (1965)). The resistance to any opposing view (which eventually became what is today dubbed the standard cosmology) was exceedingly strong during most of the nineteenth century and the early twentieth century. It is epitomized in the words of one of the pioneers of modern astrophysics, Sir Arthur Eddington (1928, p. 85), who in his authoritative monograph The Nature of the Physical World wrote: “As ascientist, I simply do not believe that the Universe ∗ E-mail: arioch@eunet.yu

–  –  –

began with a bang”.1 From the end of the Middle Ages until Hubble’s observational revolution in the third decade of the twentieth century, the stationary world view has been in one way or another dominant. This explains, among other issues, the dramatic reaction of most of the scientific community, including Lord Kelvin, Holmes, Eddington, Crookes, Jeans and others, to the discoveries of Clausius, Boltzmann and other thermodynamicists, implying a unidirectional flow of time and physical change. Interestingly enough, even during this epoch the idea – today one of most investigated issues in physics – that the thermodynamic arrow of time originates in cosmology, has occasionally surfaced (Steckline, 1983; Price, 1996, and references therein).

The power of a stationary alternative to the evolutionary models of the Universe has been reiterated in particularly colourful form during the great cosmological controversy in the late 1940s, 1950s and early 1960s (Kragh, 1996). Although during this period of conflict between the Big Bang and the classical steady-state theories numerous and very heterogeneous arguments appeared on both sides of the controversy, the argument based on the anthropic selection effect was only explicitly formulated a decade after the disagreements ended. As is well known, the debate ceased when empirical arguments persuaded by far the largest part of the cosmological community that a Universe of finite age is the only empirically acceptable concept.2 However, the argument based on the anthropic principle has been further developed during the 1980s and has gained relevance in a new and developing field of quantum cosmology (together with other aspects of anthropic reasoning). This brief note is dedicated to investigation of its origin in the ancient philosophy of nature, while the detailed consideration of its range, scope ´ and various versions will be presented in a forthcoming study (Cirkovi´, 2003).

c The modern version of the anthropic argument against the past infinite series of events (or the past temporal infinity in relationist terms; see the discussion below) has appeared in a short notice by Davies (1978) appearing in Nature. In this succinct critique of the Ellis et al. (1978) static cosmological model Davies pointed out that there is also the curious problem of why, if the Universe is infinitely old and life is concentrated in our particular corner of the cosmos, it is not inhabited by technological communities of unlimited age.





The same idea has been further developed and put on a mathematical footing by Tipler (1982). As claimed by Barrow and Tipler (1986) in their encyclopaedic monograph on anthropic principles, this is historically the first instance in which an anthropic argument has been used against cosmology containing the past temporal infinity. As we shall see in the rest of this study, this claim is only partially correct, since the thinkers in antiquity have been aware of a similar argumentation. However, it is indeed fascinating that the same argument had not been considered earlier in the course of the twentieth century. The surprise is strengthened by the fact that cosmologies postulating an infinite past in scientific or half-scientific form have existed since the very dawn of science. In addition, since ancient times a belief in the existence of other inhabited worlds has also been present, in one form or another.3 Today, the scepticism sometimes encountered against this mode of thinking is even stranger, when various (and, at least in some cases, not quite inexpensive) search for extraterrestrial intelligence (SETI) projects testify to the reasonable degree of belief in the existence of technological civilizations other than the human one. Their technological nature (the same that produces the problem Davies wrote about) is a conditio sine qua non of any sensible SETI enterprise. In this short

–  –  –

note, we shall try to recall some of the instances this argument has surfaced in the ancient cosmological thought, while leaving the deep tracing of its elements and possibly a wide survey to a subsequent work.

2 EMPEDOCLES’ UNIFORMITARIANISM AND REDUCTIONISM

An ancient echo of this type of argumentation can be recognized in the surviving fragments of some of the most distinguished Hellenic philosophers of nature. From our point of view especially interesting is the cyclic cosmology of Empedocles of Acragas (sixth to fifth century BC), in which the Universe is eternal,4 consisting of the internally immutable four classic elements, as well as two opposing forces (Love and Strife, i.e. attractive and repulsive interactions). The cyclic motion of matter in the Universe is governed by the change in relative intensities of two interactions (see the excellent discussion by O’Brien (1969)). It is interesting to note that Empedocles’ cosmology is uniformitarian, in the sense that all six basic constituents (four elements and two forces between them) are present in each instant of time in accordance with the eternal principles of mutual exchange. In some of the surviving fragments, Empedocles implies that, although this uniformitarianism may seem counterintuitive, as we see things coming into being and vanishing, this is just our special perspective (today we would say anthropocentrism) and not the inherent state of nature.5 This is strikingly similar to the uniformitarian notions present in some of the most authoritative cosmological models of the twentieth century, notably the classical steady-state theory (Balashov, 1994). The connection is strikingly relevant when the fact that the classical steady-state theory entails an infinite past is taken into account.

However, the most interesting aspect of this cosmological picture is what occurs within each individual great cosmic cycle. Probably the most lasting and controversial legacy of Empedoclean cosmology is his assertion that biological and even anthropological evolution are inherent, necessary and inseparable parts of the global cosmological evolution (Guthrie, 1969).

Thus, speaking on the four elements, he states For out of these have sprung all things that were and are and shall be – trees and men and women, beasts and birds and the fishes that dwell in the waters, yea, and the gods that live long lives and are exalted in honor.

For these things are what they are; but, running through one another, they take different shapes – so much does mixture change them.6 However, if we accept this view – which we shall call an ‘Empedoclean picture’ hereafter – that biological evolution and the appearance of consciousness and intelligence are contingent upon cosmological processes, the eternal Universe of Empedocles faces the same kind of problem as that of modern stationary cosmologies such as the classical steadystate theory or that of Ellis et al. criticized by Davies. Why then, in the supposed infinity of time, are ‘men and women, beasts and birds’ of finite, and relatively small, age? Empedocles may have perceived this himself (his mode of thinking and even his theory of metempsychosis were 4 It seems clear that Empedocles held a sort of absolutist (substantivalist) theory of the nature of time. In particular, the fragment B 16 of the Diels collection reads (according to the translation of Burnet (1908)): ‘For of a truth they (Strife and Love) were aforetime and shall be; nor ever, methinks, will boundless time be emptied of that pair.’ 5 Another pioneering contribution of Empedocles lies exactly in separation (the earliest in Western thought!) of physical nature and artifacts of human cognizance. See, for instance, the Diels fragment B 8, reading (in Burnet’s translation): ‘There is no coming into being of aught that perishes, nor any end for it in baneful death; but only mingling and change of what has been mingled. Coming into being is but a name given to these by men.’ Even more telling along the same lines are fragments B 11 and B 15.

6 Fragment B 21 in Diels (1983), translation by Burnet (1908). Similar content can be found in B 20.

´ ´ 882 M. M. CIRKOVIC closer to the modern anthropic mode of thinking than those of most of the later physicists and philosophers), and he evades the problem in the only natural way that he can: by postulating two singular states in the beginning and in the middle of each of his great cycles. These singular states are moments (in absolute time!) of complete dominance of either Love (an ancient equivalent of the modern initial and/or final singularities) or Strife (no true equivalent, but similar to the modern version of heat death in the ever-expanding cosmological models; see for instance Davies (1994)). In these states the life, with its complex organizational structure, is impossible and therefore they serve as termini for the duration of any individual history of life and intelligence. The maximal duration of any form of life and/or intelligence is determined exclusively by cosmological laws. Therefore, there are no arbitrarily old beings, and anthropic argument is inapplicable.

It is worth noting that the Empedoclean reductionist picture of the relationship between biological and psychological processes on the one hand, and physical and cosmological processes on the other, has become quite common in the ancient philosophical thought after Empedocles.

It is also present, for instance, in cosmologies postulating finite age of the Universe, or at least a finite duration of world histories, such as in Anaxagoras’ system. According to the testimony of Diodorus (I 7, 7), Euripides has, in his lost tragedy Melanippa, described – clearly under the influence of his teacher Anaxagoras – the rise of plants, animals and humans as an ultimate consequence of separation of the heavens and the Earth from their primordial unity; which is another suprisingly modern picture. With the rise of Socrates, and subsequently Platonic and Aristotelian philosophy, and in particular during the age of faith, this line of thinking became discontinued; in a sense it has only inherited worthy successors in the modern thought contained in philosophical considerations of both quantum mechanics and cosmology (see for example Schr¨ dinger (1944); Barrow and Tipler (1986) and Smolin (1997)). We cannot treat o these reissues of the Empedoclean picture in the course of this study. However, it is worth noting that the problems facing such contingency of biological upon cosmological processes have also been noted in antiquity by several famous authors.

3 REPETITIONS IN ANTIQUITY

In the very first chapter of the immortal history of Thucydides, there is a famous statement that before his time – that is about 450 BC – nothing of importance (σ υ µεγ αλα γ ευεσ θ αι) had happened in history. This startling statement has been correctly called ‘outrageous’ by Spengler (1918) and used to demonstrate the essentially mythological character of ancient Greek historiography (see also Cornford (1965)). It may indeed be outrageous from the modern perspective, but it does motivate a set of deeper questions, ultimately dealing with cosmology.



Pages:   || 2 |


Similar works:

«Schriftenreihe der Forschungsgruppe Metropolenforschung des Forschungsschwerpunkts Technik Arbeit Umwelt am Wissenschaftszentrum Berlin für Sozialforschung FS II 01-504 Die Großstädte und das Geistesleben von Georg Simmel Zur Geschichte einer Antipathie Dietmar Jazbinsek Wissenschaftszentrum Berlin für Sozialforschung gGmbH (WZB) Reichpietschufer 50, D-10785 Berlin Tel. (030)-25 491-0 Fax (030)-25 491-254 od. -684 Die Großstädte und das Geistesleben von Georg Simmel Zur Geschichte einer...»

«Louis Hyman 356 Ives Hall (617) 942 1033 Cornell University Lrh62@cornell.edu Ithaca, NY 14852-3901 lhyman@gmail.com Appointments Assistant Professor of History, ILR School, Cornell University Department of Labor Relations, Law and History Member: Program in American Studies Education 2007 Ph.D. in History, Harvard University 1999 B.A. in History and Mathematics with honors, Columbia University Research Honors, Fellowships, Grants, and Awards 2014 Organization of American Historians,...»

«Getting Schmedieval: Of Manuscript and Film Prologues, Paratexts, and Parodies Richard Burt © F ilm critics and historians have by and large rejected what has come to be known as the fidelity model of criticism when discussing films about history or set in an historical period, arguing that it is better to treat these films as films than to evaluate them in terms of how faithfully and how accurately they portray history.1 Instead of examining what a given film says about the medieval past, for...»

«Кафедра Публикация подготовлена в рамках поддержанного РГНФ научного проекта №14-04-00371 МИМИЧЕСКАя РОЛь Лиз Нобле в опере «Немая из Портичи» Коротко об авторе About the author Жесткова Ольга Владимировна, кандидат искусствоведения, Olga Vladimirovna Zhestkova, Cand. of Art Studies (Phd), доцент кафедры...»

«Forests AMERICAN A History of Resiliency and Recovery ISSUE S SE RIE S DOUGLAS W. MacCLEERY AMERICAN FORESTS FOREST HISTORY SOCIETY ISSUES SERIES The Forest History Society was founded in 1946. Since that time, the Society, through its research, reference, and publications programs, has advanced forest and conservation history scholarship. At the same time, it has translated that scholarship into formats useful for people with policy and management responsibilities. For seven decades the...»

«The Unconventional War: Parallels between the Combat Experience in Vietnam and Iraq BY JOSHUA AKERS Prior to the current operations inside Afghanistan, the conflict in Vietnam was considered “America’s longest war,” lasting from 1950 to 1975.1 While American combat troops were not committed in Vietnam until the summer of 1965, the long stalemate and the withdrawal of troops in the following years weighed heavily on American minds afterward.2 The war in Iraq, or in military parlance,...»

«The Negative Church of Modernity: Siegfried Kracauer, Secularization, and Cultural Crisis in Weimar Germany by Harry Todd Craver A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of History University of Toronto Copyright by Harry Todd Craver 2011 The Negative Church of Modernity: Siegfried Kracauer, Secularization, and Cultural Crisis in Weimar Germany Harry Todd Craver Doctor of Philosophy Department of History University of Toronto...»

«The ageing of modern socieTies: crisis or opporTuniTy? – paTricia Thane / 333 THE AGEING OF MODERN SOCIETIES: HISTORIA 396 ISSN 0719-0719 CRISIS OR OPPORTUNITY?* Nº 2 2013 [333-349] EL ENVEJECIMIENTO DE LAS SOCIEDADES MODERNAS: ¿CRISIS U OPORTUNIDAD? Patricia Thane King’s College of London, Reino Unido pat.thane@kcl.ac.uk Abstract In all modern societies more people are living to later ages. This is widely seen as a crisis, imposing an increasing burden of costs due to the needs of older...»

«I Ladins dles Dolomites Die Dolomitenladiner Unterrichtseinheit über die ladinische Sprachgemeinschaft herausgegeben von der Gesellschaft für bedrohte Vöker Lia por i popui manacês Mit freundlicher Unterstützung der Consulta per i problems ladins dl Comun de Bulsan © 2001-2005 Einleitung Wenn man deutsche und italienische Südtiroler nach den Ladinern fragt, so ist die Antwort meist recht karg. Das Wissen um Ladinien und seine Bewohner ist ziemlich gering, die Vorstellungen recht...»

«Das Jahrbuch uber die Fortschritte der Mathematik. Ruckblick und Ausblick. 1 Von Emil Lampe. Wenn ich den angekundigten Vortrag uber das von mir geleitete Jahrbuch uber die Fortschritte der Mathematik jetzt zu halten beginne, so mu ich mich zuerst entschuldigen, da ich damit in einer scheinbar personlichen Angelegenheit das Wort nehme. Das Jahrbuch bespricht aber alle Erscheinungen der mathematischen Literatur jedes einzelnen Jahres daher ist es fur die Geschichte der Mathematik, die ja ein...»

«Jürate Trilupaitiene, XVI-XVII a. Lietuvos baznytine muzyka: konfe­ siniq s~üdziq poveikis jos raidai [Lithuanian church musie of the 16th and 17 century: The influence of religious movements on its develop­ ment] Habilitation, Vilnius 1999 Introduction The work summarizes the author's long-term scientific research, parts of which have been presented in scientific papers. in Lithuania and foreign publications. The topic has not previously been researched, important not only for the...»

«ON ARCHIMEDEAN ROOTS IN TORRICELLI’S MECHANICS Raffaele Pisano Centre François Viète, Université de Nantes, France e–mail: pisanoraffaele@iol.it Danilo Capecchi Università di Roma “La Sapienza” Via Antonio Gramsci 53, 00197 Roma, Italy e–mail: danilo.capecchi@uniroma1.it Abstract In recent papers we analyzed the historical development of the foundations of the centres of gravity theory during the Renaissance. Using these works as a starting point, we shall briefly present a...»





 
<<  HOME   |    CONTACTS
2016 www.abstract.xlibx.info - Free e-library - Abstract, dissertation, book

Materials of this site are available for review, all rights belong to their respective owners.
If you do not agree with the fact that your material is placed on this site, please, email us, we will within 1-2 business days delete him.